![](https://blogger.googleusercontent.com/img/b/R29vZ2xl/AVvXsEiHaEP_amhk_iACfblobdb4V2iuRSInJ9n45jFor0vPy-GRe1fQSfF8PAbp5dpe3CONW62QwD1bSVWUQdlWvYF6MnPZsOyTqneqE5Zc9EcyqEcfzw4tscve4FMpfqXT_lYSvqt2kV0gbP8/s1600/Jim+for+web.jpg)
The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2 ed.)
From the Greek word for goal, task, completion, or
perfection. Teleological explanations attempt to account for things and
features by appeal to their contribution to optimal states, or the normal
functioning, or the attainment of goals, of wholes or systems they belong to.
Socrates' story (in Plato's Phaedo) of how he wanted to understand things in
terms of what is best is an early discussion of teleology. Another is
Aristotle's discussion of ‘final cause’ explanations in terms of that for the
sake of which something is, acts, or is acted upon. Such explanations are parodied
in Voltaire's Candide.
There are many cases in which an item's contribution to a
desirable result does not explain its occurrence. For example, what spring rain
does for crops does not explain why it rains in the spring. But suppose we
discovered that some object's features were designed and maintained by an
intelligent creator to enable it to accomplish some purpose. Then an
understanding of a feature's contribution to that purpose could help us explain
its presence without mistakenly assuming that everything is as it is because of
the effects it causes. There are many things (e.g. well-designed clocks in good
working order) known to have been produced by intelligent manufacturers for
well-understood purposes, whose features can, therefore, be explained in this
way. But if all teleological explanation presupposes intelligent design, only
creationists could accept teleological explanations of natural things, and only
conspiracy theorists could accept teleological explanations of economic and
social phenomena.
Teleological explanations which do not presuppose that what
is to be explained is the work of an intelligent agent are to be found in
biology, economics, and elsewhere. Their justification typically involves two
components: an analysis of the function of the item to be explained and an
aetiological account.
Functional analysis seeks to determine what contribution the
item to be explained makes to some main activity, to the proper functioning, or
to the well-being or preservation, of the organism, object, or system it
belongs to. For example, given what is known about the contribution of normal
blood circulation to the main activities and the well-being of animals with
hearts, the structure and behaviour of the heart lead physiologists to identify
its function with its contribution to circulation. Given the function of part
of an organism, the function of a subpart (e.g. some nerve-ending in the heart)
can be identified with its contribution—if any—to the function of the part
(e.g. stimulating heart contractions). Important empirical problems in biology
and the social sciences and equally important conceptual problems in the
philosophy of science arise from questions about the evaluation of ascriptions
of purposes and functions.
![](https://blogger.googleusercontent.com/img/b/R29vZ2xl/AVvXsEh9TVPmH7WtJ-HOxwPshtkCVrOjgZAn5DNeshdfmvLfmHUhhhg0jYu4254wDRVHiePQsgyywYb54Wzp8eLLgdXhsK15RLdwsZ0TeugVX0toewSSj8Ea3lV9UjAoM6bt8qtaV5N13fyLrWU/s1600/9780191727474.jpg)
Bibliography
- A. Ariew, R. Cummins, and M. Perlman (eds.), Functions
(Oxford, 2002).
- Morton O. Beckner, Biological Ways of Thought (Berkeley,
Calif., 1968), chs. 6–8.
- Larry Wright, ‘Functions’, Christopher Bourse, ‘Wright on
Functions’ Robert Cummins, ‘Functional Analysis’ (along with further references
to standard literature), in Elliott Sober (ed.), Conceptual Issues in
Evolutionary Biology (Cambridge, Mass., 1984).
No comments:
Post a Comment