Jan Narveson, Distinguished Professor Emeritus of Philosophy, University of Waterloo in Ontario, Canada.
Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics (Second Edition) 2012, Pages 51–55
Egoism and altruism come in two forms: psychological and normative
– theories about what we do and what we ought to do. Psychological egoism
succumbs to the distinction between interests in ourselves, strictly, and
interests that are ours but not directed at ourselves. The first, egoism
proper, is clearly false. The second allows altruism. Ethical egoism falls
before the familiar observation that exclusive devotion to ourselves does not
make us as happy as a life of love and involvement. Moral egoism is irrational,
asking us to sanction actions by others that are strongly against our own
interests.
Psychological versus Ethical Egoism
Egoism and altruism are subject even more than usual in philosophy
to crucial ambiguities that must be sorted out before one can say anything
helpful. There are two types of egoism – psychological and ethical. The first
is a theory about human motivations: What makes us tick? According to egoism,
we are actuated entirely by self-interest, even when it appears to be
otherwise. Altruism, of course, denies this. However, the second is a normative
theory – a theory about what we should do. It says that we should, or ought to,
act only in our own interest. How these are related is perhaps the central
question for the subject.
Substantive versus Tautological Psychological Egoism
Just what is self-interest? Here, the groundbreaking work of Joseph
Butler (1692–1752) paves the way for us. Does ‘self-interest’ mean interests in
ourselves or only interests of ourselves? Everything hangs on that one-word
difference.
Interests in ourselves are interests that one’s own self have
certain things, held to be good by the agent – things that can be identified
and had independently of the goods of others. For example, hunger is a desire
for food in one’s own stomach; desires for physical comfort, for optimal
temperature, or for the absence of pain in one’s own body are further examples.
The desire to feel pleasure and avoid pain is the most widely held candidate
for the status of fundamental motivator of all action. Interests in others, by
contrast, would be such desires as love or hatred, where we are essentially
directing our actions toward the production of certain states of other people.
The kind of psychological egoism holding that we are exclusively motivated by
the first kind of interests may be called strict or substantive.
Interests of ourselves, on the other hand, simply refer to whose
interests they are but not at all to what the interests are taken in – what
they are aimed at affecting, either in or outside of ourselves. As Butler
pointed out, it is trivial to say that all action is motivated by interests or
desires of the agent – that is what makes them the agent’s actions at all. We
might call this tautologous psychological egoism. By contrast, it is not at all
trivial to say that the object of our actions is only to produce certain
conditions of ourselves. Of course, the situation is complicated by the fact
that we can get pleasure, for example, from our perception of the condition of
certain other people, or even of all other people. When we do so, are we
motivated by the prospect of pleasure from our relations to those people? If
so, is that to be accounted egoism, despite the fact that the source of our
pleasure in these cases is the pleasures – or perhaps the pains – of others? On
the face of it, we need yet another distinction. This would be between theories
that deny that we even get pleasure from other-regarding acts and theories that
accept this but insist that it is only because of the pleasure we get from them
that we perform them.
Superficial versus Deep Theories
The question whether psychological egoism may be true becomes very
difficult, however, when we distinguish between what we may call superficial
or, in the terminology of contemporary philosophers of mind, folk-psychological
versions of the theory and what we may call deep theories.
At the superficial level, psychological egoism is, as Butler also
pointed out, overwhelmingly implausible. People make huge sacrifices for those
they love, including sacrifice of their very lives. Moreover, they sometimes go
out of their way to do evils to other people even at the cost of ruining their
own lives in the process.
Deep theories are quite another matter. No one can claim to have
refuted the view that there is some variable within the soul – or the nervous
system – such that all actions really do maximize it, regardless of all else in
the environment. To make this work, of course, it would have to be noted that
other factors in the environment would certainly interact with that variable,
whatever it is.
The most popular candidate for what we may be trying to maximize,
no doubt, is net pleasure: the quantity, pleasure minus pain, or more
plausibly, of positive affect minus negative affect (or plus negative affect if
we think of the latter as a negative quantity). Perhaps the man who falls on
the grenade to save his comrades reckons that he could not live with himself if
he did not do it. Perhaps, as Kant supposed, our self-interested motivations
are hidden from our own view so that despite our pretentions to altruism, we
are really always acting in our own interest after all. However, once the
common-sense idea that pleasure and pain are things we are aware of is
abandoned, the situation changes radically. We then need a good theory
explaining just what the quantity in question is really supposed to be –
electrical magnitudes in brain cells, perhaps? We would need to explain how the
theory is to be assessed in empirical terms. Clearly, appraising any such view
will be very difficult. In this article, we will not further discuss such
possibilities. Regarding commonsense distinctions, psychological egoism may
surely be dismissed as simply wrong and based entirely on the confusion between
egoism as a substantive view and egoism in its tautological form.
Varieties of Motivation
A major complication in the discussion of this issue is just how we
are to count certain human motivations in relation to the egoism versus
altruism categories. There are many cases in which someone acts without
obviously intending to promote his or her own pleasure but also without
obviously intending to benefit anyone else. Suppose that Henry conceives a
passion for building a replica of the Great Pyramid in his backyard. He labors
mightily and for years, often with considerable pain, and it damages his health
considerably in the process. Is he here pursuing pleasure? If we say so, then
the notion of pleasure has become very broad. Is he doing it for anyone else’s
benefit? Not obviously, at least.
For the purposes of this article, we account motivations that seem
to be for the pursuit of states of affairs having no evident connection with
either the agent’s or anyone else’s benefit as being, nevertheless, for the
agent’s benefit inasmuch as they are attempts to attain something that he or
she wants, or at least feels impelled, to do. If this is not very much like
satisfying hunger or sex, that is the point. The category of the
self-interested is hugely broad so that the explanatory value of appeals to
self-interest is rather low.
Altruism – Psychological Version
If psychological egoism has its difficulties, psychological
altruism is also problematic. Again, discussion requires more care with
definitions. Altruism may be understood as concern with others – but how much,
and which others? At the opposite extreme from egoism is the view that we only act
for the sake of others, and we do so for the sake of all others. To the
author’s knowledge, no one has ever seriously advocated such a theory. The
English philosopher David Hume (1711–76) hypothesized that some altruism is to
be found in every human – a general feeling for all other humans, at the least.
Taken as a superficial-level generalization about people, this is fairly
plausible, and it would be even more so if we said that nearly everyone is at
least slightly altruistic regarding most other humans. But it is, of course,
not very precise, and how to describe it more accurately, and account for it,
is an interesting question. Interaction with one’s mother in infancy, for
example, and later with peers, may play a role in the genesis of such dispositions.
Ethical Incompatibility with Psychological Egoism
We now turn to the ethical versions of egoism. Here, we do well to
begin by recognizing that for ethical egoism to be meaningful at all, strict
psychological egoism, at least in its superficial forms, must be false. If
Jones is unable to seek anyone’s well-being but his own, then there is
obviously no point in telling him that he ought to be seeking someone else’s.
Ought, as philosophers state, implies can. (Even here, the distinction of
shallow from deep theories is essential because it is by no means clear that
ethics is incompatible with deep self-interest. Possibly, totally altruistic
behavior is best for oneself, and the truly selfish person is the saint or the
hero who devotes his or her life to helping others.)
Ethical versus Moral Egoism
For the purposes of this article, we are assuming the plain or
superficial level of discussion, which we all understand fairly well, and ask
whether ethical egoism is plausible in those terms. However, now we must make
still another distinction, and again a crucial one – this time with the word
‘ethical.’ By ethical, do we refer to the general theory of how to live? Or do
we mean, much more narrowly, rules for the group? Egoism will look very
different in these two very different contexts. If the question is, should I
aim to live the best life I can? it is extremely difficult to answer in the
negative. Each one of us should, surely, try to live the best life we can – the
most satisfying, most rewarding, most pleasant, etc., life we can manage. Of
course, this leads to the very large question of what the ultimate values of
life are and how to maximize them – what sort of life will do that. For
example, as already noted, it is quite possible that a life of self-sacrifice
is nevertheless the most fulfilling or rewarding. Perhaps it is even the most
pleasant, although this seems to strain the idea. Furthermore, perhaps there
are other values more important than pleasure.
Egoism Not Necessarily Selfish
As the previous discussion suggests, egoism as a theory of life may
be very different from what the word at first suggests. When we think of
egoists, we think, first, of people who are highly self-centered, who tend to
ignore others and their needs, even their rights. Another word for this is
egotism, which is a personality trait rather than a theory. At the extreme, we
think of the psychopath, who will kill, rape, steal, lie, and cheat without
compunction in order to achieve certain narrow ends for himself – usually the
increment of his monetary income, but by no means always. However, does the
psychopath live a good life? Would someone setting out to live the happiest,
most rewarding life he or she can become psychopathic? That is extremely
implausible. The wisdom of philosophers through the millennia has been uniform
on this point: If you want to be happy yourself, then you need friends, loved
ones, and associates, and you need to treat all these people with respect, most
of them with kindness as well, and some of them with real love.
This last discussion shows the difficulty of contrasting egoism and
altruism at this level. Should we literally sacrifice our own overall happiness
or well-being for others? Which others? And especially, of course, why? To
suggest that one should do such a thing – if it is possible – seems to be to
suggest that those other persons are somehow superior to you. Why should we
believe any such thing?
Notice that as a universal theory, this last would run into logical
difficulties. Whatever ‘worthy’ means, if A is more worthy than B, then B is
less worthy than A, by definition. Thus, it is impossible for everyone to be
more worthy than everyone else.
Egoism and Morality
At this point, let us turn to the other member of the distinction I
have made – morality. To talk about morality is to talk of what should be the
rules governing the general behavior of the group. One question this
immediately raises is, which group? Without getting too involved in the
question of cultural relativism, let us supply two answers to this question:
(1) the group in question – that is, the group of which the persons we are
addressing are members, with whom they interact, fairly frequently; and (2) the
group consisting of literally everybody – all humans. Again, most classic
philosophers assumed the latter, and the assumption is certainly not an
unrealistic one.
What matters, however, is that we are now addressing the question
not simply what to do in life generally but what to do in relation to our
fellows: How do we carry on our dealings with them, our interactions? It is
when we address this question that egoism, in any sense of that word in which
it is meaningful, becomes enormously implausible. For if we think of the egoist
as the one who pursues only his or her own interest, regardless of others, so
that our image is of near-psychopathic behavior, then to recommend that as the
rule for a group seems completely absurd, even unintelligible. Egoism, again
speaking at the superficial level, must address the question of conflicts of
interest. If A’s interests are incompatible with B’s – meaning, simply, that if
A achieves what he is after, then B is frustrated in his pursuit of what he is
after – then a rule addressed to the two of them, telling them both to ignore
the other and go for it, is silly. If both try to follow it, at least one will
fail. In fact, most likely both of them will, especially if we take into
account any aspects of their values that extend beyond the narrow one that was
the subject of conflict. For example, if the two come to blows, then at least one
and probably both will suffer injuries that they would prefer not to have
inflicted on them. A rule for a group, if it is to be even remotely plausible,
will have to do better than that. When there are conflicts, it is going to have
to tell us who is in the right and who is in the wrong – who gets to go ahead
and who has to back down.
Trying to incorporate real egoism, of the first kind identified at
the outset, into the very matter of moral rules is an invitation to conceptual
disaster. That Jones ought to do x and Smith ought to do y, even though Jones’s
doing x entails Smith’s not doing y, is rightly regarded as a nonsense rule.
Two boxers in the ring ought both, of course, to try to win, but to say that
both ought to win is nonsense because by definition that is impossible. A
morality for all, therefore, cannot look like directions to the cheering
section for one of the fighters but, rather, like the rule book for boxing,
which tells both of them that they have only so many minutes between breaks, that
they may not hit below the belt, and so forth. Morality in our second and
narrower sense of the term consists of the rules for large, natural groups –
that is, groups of people who happen, for whatever reason, to come in contact
with each other rather than groups that come together intentionally for
specific purposes. For such groups, the rules are going to have to be impartial
rather than loaded in favor of one person or set of persons as against another.
Thus, such rules simply cannot be egoistic.
Altruism and Morality
Can they be altruistic? That gets us to our last question. Should
the rules for groups tell everyone to love everyone else, as fully as if
everyone were one’s dear sibling or spouse? The answer to this is surely in the
negative, as Nietzsche pointed out. One or at most a very few lovers or loved
ones is all any of us can handle. Truly to love someone, we must elevate that
person well above the crowd, pay more attention to him or her than to others –
not merely an equal amount – and so on. Altruism construed as the general love
of humankind, therefore, simply cannot be using the term ‘love’ in its full
normal sense. A doctrine of general altruism must retreat very far from that.
Indeed, it is clear that general altruism has exactly the same problem as
general egoism: Both are shipwrecked as soon as we see the inevitable
asymmetries and partialities necessarily involved in love, whether of oneself
or anyone else.
How far, then, do we retreat? Here, a variety of answers have been
given, and we need to make one last distinction – between two departments or
branches of morals. One branch is stern, and associated with justice, rules
that are to be enforced by such heavy-duty procedures as punishments; the other
is associated with commendations and praise, warm sentiments, and so forth.
Following Kant, we may call these respectively the theory of justice and the
theory of virtue or, in a slightly different vein, justice and charity. One is,
in short, the morality of the stick, whereas the other is the morality of the
carrot. That is, it is appropriate to reinforce the rules of justice by such
methods as punishment, including incarceration, or even death. However, the
other is to be encouraged – we cheer for those who do well but we do not resort
to punishment for lesser performance of those actions that are merely virtuous
rather than downright required.
Now, our question may be put thus: Is altruism to be regarded as
figuring prominently in, or perhaps even constituting the basis of, either of
these, both, or neither of these?
Again, it is highly plausible to deny altruism any significant role
in the first. If you and I are enemies, it is pretty pointless to tell us to
love each other, but it is not at all pointless to tell us to draw some lines
and then stay on our side of them. For example, we are to refrain from killing,
stealing from, lying to, cheating, maiming, or otherwise damaging even if we
hate each other. We shall all do better if we simply rule out such actions.
This is negative morality, the morality of thou shalt not, and it applies
between absolutely everyone and absolutely everyone else, be they friends or
enemies or strangers, with the sole qualification being that those who
themselves are guilty of transgressing one of those restrictions may be
eligible for punishment. It is absurd to point to love as the basis of such
rules. Rather, it is our interests, considered in relation to how things are
and how other people are, that undergird these vital rules of social life.
On the other hand, when it comes to helping those in need, showing
kindness to people, being thoughtful, helpful, supportive, and so on – in
short, of being, in the words of Hume, agreeable and useful to others – it is
more plausible to ascribe this to sentiment – to some degree of altruism. Even
so, it is by no means clear that it is necessary because in being nice to
others, we inspire them to be nice to us, and so even considerations of
self-interest fairly narrowly construed will teach us the value of these
other-regarding virtues. However, it is also plausible to suggest that we
admire and praise people who go well beyond the minimum in these respects: We
put the Mother Theresas of the world, the heroic life-savers, those who go the
extra mile and then some, on pedestals, and rightly so. As Hume conjectures, it
seems implausible to confine those tendencies to self-interest in any narrow
sense of that word.
Conclusion
To get a clear view of this long-discussed subject, we need to make
several important distinctions. First, we must distinguish the normative or
ethical from the psychological version of egoism. Second, in both cases, we
need to distinguish between egoism in the narrow sense in which it entails an
interest exclusively in the self, defined as independent of all others, and the
much broader – really vacuous – sense in which it essentially means that one
acts only on one’s own desires, whatever their objects. Third, we must
distinguish shallow or superficial from deep versions. Finally, we must
distinguish ethics in the very broad sense of one’s general view of life from
morality, in the much narrower sense of a canon or set of rules for the conduct
of everyone in society. It is then seen that ethical egoism says essentially
nothing, whereas moral egoism proposes what is obviously unacceptable.