By Sir Isaiah Berlin (1909-1997)
Initially published in The New York Review of Books, October 3, 1996
Initially published in The New York Review of Books, October 3, 1996
What is it to have good judgment in politics? What is it to
be politically wise, or gifted, to be a political genius, or even to be no more
than politically competent, to know how to get things done? Perhaps one way of
looking for the answer is by considering what we are saying when we denounce
statesmen, or pity them, for not possessing these qualities. We sometimes
complain that they are blinded by prejudice or passion, but blinded to what? We
say that they don’t understand the times they live in, or that they are
resisting something called “the logic of the facts,” or are “trying to put the
clock back,” or that “history is against them,” or that they are ignorant or
incapable of learning, or else unpractical idealists, visionaries, Utopians,
hypnotized by the dream of some fabulous past or some unrealizable future.
All such expressions and metaphors seem to presuppose that
there is something to know (of which the critic has some notion) which these
unfortunate persons have somehow not managed to grasp, whether it is the
inexorable movement of some cosmic clock which no man can alter, or some
pattern of things in time or space, or in some more mysterious medium—”the
realm of the Spirit” or “ultimate reality”—which one must first understand if
one is to avoid frustration.
But what is this knowledge? Is it knowledge of a science?
Are there really laws to be discovered, rules to be learned? Can statesmen be
taught something called political science—the science of the relationships of
human beings to each other and to their environment—which consists, like other
sciences, of systems of verified hypotheses, organized under laws, that enable
one, by the use of further experiment and observation, to discover other facts,
and to verify new hypotheses?
Certainly that was the notion, either concealed or open, of
both Hobbes and Spinoza, each in his own fashion, and of their followers—a
notion that grew more and more powerful in the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries, when the natural sciences acquired enormous prestige, and attempts
were made to maintain that anything not capable of being reduced to a natural
science could not properly be called knowledge at all. The more ambitious and
extreme scientific determinists, such as Holbach, Helvétius, and La Mettrie,
used to think that, given enough knowledge of universal human nature and of the
laws of social behavior, and enough knowledge of the state of given human
beings at a given time, one could scientifically calculate how these human
beings, or at any rate large groups of them—entire societies or classes—would
behave under some other given set of circumstances. It was argued, and this
seemed reasonable enough at the time, that just as knowledge of mechanics was
indispensable to engineers or architects or inventors, so knowledge of social
mechanics was necessary for anyone—statesmen, for example—who wished to get
large bodies of men to do this or that. For without it, what had they to rely
on but casual impressions, half-remembered, unverified recollections,
guesswork, mere rules of thumb, unscientific hypotheses? One must, no doubt,
make do with these if one has no proper scientific method at one’s disposal;
but one should realize that this is no better than unorganized conjectures
about nature made by primitive peoples, or by the inhabitants of Europe during
the Dark Ages—grotesquely inadequate tools superseded by the earliest advances
of true science. And there are those (in institutions of higher learning) who
have thought this, and think this still, in our own times.
Less ambitious thinkers, influenced by the fathers of the
life sciences at the turn of the eighteenth century, conceived of the science
of society as being rather more like a kind of social anatomy. To be a good
doctor it is necessary, but not sufficient, to know anatomical theory. For one
must also know how to apply it to specific cases—to particular patients,
suffering from particular forms of a particular disease. This cannot be wholly
learned from books or professors, it requires considerable personal experience
and natural aptitude. Nevertheless, neither experience nor natural gifts can
ever be a complete substitute for knowledge of a developed science—pathology,
say, or anatomy. To know only the theory might not be enough to enable one to
heal the sick, but to be ignorant of it is fatal. By analogy with medicine,
such faults as bad political judgment, lack of realism, Utopianism, attempts to
arrest progress, and so on were duly conceived as deriving from ignorance or
defiance of the laws of social development—laws of social biology (which
conceives of society as an organism rather than a mechanism), or of the
corresponding science of politics.
The scientifically inclined philosophers of the eighteenth
century believed passionately in just such laws, and tried to account for human
behavior wholly in terms of the identifi-able effects of education, of natural
environment, and of the calculable results of the play of appetites and
passions. However, this approach turned out to explain so small a part of the
actual behavior of human beings at times when it seemed most in need of
explanation—during and after the Jacobin Terror—and failed so conspicuously to
predict or analyze such major phenomena as the growth and violence of
nationalism, the uniqueness of, and the conflicts between, various cultures,
and the events leading to wars and revolutions, and displayed so little
understanding of what may broadly be called spiritual or emotional life
(whether of individuals or of whole peoples), and the unpredictable play of
irrational factors, that new hypotheses inevitably entered the field, each
claiming to overthrow all the others, and to be the last and definitive word on
the subject.
Messianic preachers—prophets—such as Saint-Simon, Fourier,
Comte, dogmatic thinkers such as Hegel, Marx, Spengler, historically-minded
theological thinkers from Bossuet to Toynbee, the popularizers of Darwin, the
adaptors of this or that dominant school of sociology or psychology—all have
attempted to step into the breach caused by the failure of the
eighteenth-century philosophers to construct a proper, successful science of
society. Each of these new nineteenth-century apostles laid some claim to
exclusive possession of the truth. What they all have in common is the belief
that there is one great universal pattern, and one unique method of
apprehending it, knowledge of which would have saved statesmen many an error,
and humanity many a hideous tragedy.
It was not exactly denied that such statesmen as Colbert, or
Richelieu, or Washington, or Pitt, or Bismarck, seem to have done well enough
without this knowledge, just as bridges had obviously been built before the
principles of mechanics were discovered, and diseases had been cured by men who
appeared to know no anatomy. It was admitted that much could be—and had
been—achieved by the inspired guesses of individual men of genius, and by their
instinctive skills; but, so it was argued, particularly toward the end of the
nineteenth century, there was no need to look to so precarious a source of
light. The principles upon which these great men acted, even though they may
not have known it, so some optimistic sociologists have maintained, can be
extracted and reduced to an accurate science, very much as the principles of
biology or mechanics must once have been established.
According to this view, political judgment need never again
be a matter of instinct and flair and sudden illuminations and strokes of
unanalyzable genius; rather it should henceforth be built upon the foundations
of indubitable knowledge. Opinions might differ about whether this new
knowledge was empirical or a priori, whether it derived its authority from the
methods of natural science or from metaphysics; but in either form it amounted
to what Herbert Spencer called the sciences of social statics and social
dynamics. Those who applied it were social engineers; the mysterious art of
government was to be mysterious no longer: it could be taught, learned,
applied; it was a matter of professional competence and specialization.
This thesis would be more plausible if the newly discovered
laws did not, as a rule, turn out either to be ancient truisms—such as that
most revolutions are followed by reaction (which amounts to not much more than
the virtual tautology that most movements come to an end at some time, and are
then followed by something else, often in some opposite direction)—or else to
be constantly upset, and violently upset, by events, leaving the theoretical
systems in ruins. Perhaps nobody did so much to undermine confidence in a
dependable science of human relations as the great tyrants of our day—Lenin,
Stalin, Hitler. If belief in the laws of history and “scientific socialism”
really did help Lenin or Stalin, it helped them not so much as a form of
knowledge, but in the way that a fanatical faith in almost any dogma can be of
help to determined men, by justifying ruthless acts and suppressing doubts and
scruples.
Between them, Stalin and Hitler left scarcely stone upon
stone of the once splendid edifice of the inexorable laws of history. Hitler,
after all, almost succeeded in his professed aim of undoing the results of the
French Revolution. The Russian Revolution violently twisted the whole of
Western society out of what, until that time, seemed to most observers a fairly
orderly course—twisted it into an irregular movement, followed by a dramatic
collapse, foretold as little by Marxist as by any other “scientific” prophets.
It is easy enough to arrange the past in a symmetrical way—Voltaire’s famous
cynical epigram to the effect that history is so many tricks played upon the
dead is not as superficial as it seems.(1) A true science, though, must be able
not merely to rearrange the past but to predict the future. To classify facts,
to order them in neat patterns, is not quite yet a science.
We are told that the great earthquake that destroyed Lisbon
in the mid-eighteenth century shook Voltaire’s faith in inevitable human
progress. Similarly the great destructive political upheavals of our own time
have instilled terrible doubts about the feasibility of a reliable science of
human behavior for the guidance of men of action—be they industrialists or
social-welfare officers or statesmen. The subject evidently had to be
re-examined afresh: the assumption that an exact science of social behavior was
merely a matter of time and ingenuity no longer seemed quite so self-evident.
What method should this science pursue? Clearly not deductive: there existed no
accepted axioms from which the whole of human behavior could be deduced by means
of agreed logical rules. Not even the most dogmatic theologian would claim as
much as that. Inductive, then? Laws based on the survey of a large collection
of empirical data? Or on hypothetical-deductive methods not very easily
applicable to the complexities of human affairs?
In theory, no doubt, such laws should have been
discoverable, but in practice this looked less promising. If I am a statesman
faced with an agonizing choice of possible courses of action in a critical
situation, will I really find it useful—even if I can afford to wait that long
for the answer—to employ a team of specialists in political science to assemble
for me from past history all kinds of cases analogous to my situation, from
which I or they must then abstract what these cases have in common, deriving
from this exercise relevant laws of human behavior? The instances for such
induction—or for the construction of hypotheses intended to systematize
historical knowledge—would, because human experience is so various, not be
numerous; and the dismissal even from these instances of all that is unique to
each, and the retention only of that which is common, would produce a very
thin, generalized residue, and one far too unspecific to be of much help in a
practical dilemma.
Obviously what matters is to understand a particular
situation in its full uniqueness, the particular men and events and dangers,
the particular hopes and fears which are actively at work in a particular place
at a particular time: in Paris in 1791, in Petrograd in 1917, in Budapest in
1956, in Prague in 1968, or in Moscow in 1991. We need not attend
systematically to whatever it is that these have in common with other events
and other situations, which may resemble them in some respects, but may happen
to lack exactly that which makes all the difference at a particular moment, in
a particular place. If I am driving a car in desperate haste, and come to a
rickety-looking bridge, and must make up my mind whether it will bear my
weight, some knowledge of the principles of engineering would no doubt be
useful. But even so I can scarcely afford to stop to survey and calculate. To
be useful to me in a crisis such knowledge must have given rise to a
semi-instinctive skill—like the ability to read without simultaneous awareness
of the rules of the language.
Still, in engineering some laws can, after all, be
formulated, even though I do not need to keep them constantly in mind. In the
realm of political action, laws are far and few indeed: skills are everything.
What makes statesmen, like drivers of cars, successful is that they do not
think in general terms—that is, they do not primarily ask themselves in what
respect a given situation is like or unlike other situations in the long course
of human history (which is what historical sociologists, or theologians in
historical clothing, such as Vico or Toynbee, are fond of doing). Their merit
is that they grasp the unique combination of characteristics that constitute
this particular situation—this and no other. What they are said to be able to
do is to understand the character of a particular movement, of a particular
individual, of a unique state of affairs, of a unique atmosphere, of some
particular combination of economic, political, personal factors; and we do not
readily suppose that this capacity can literally be taught.
We speak of, say, an exceptional sensitiveness to certain
kinds of fact; we resort to metaphors. We speak of some people as possessing
antennae, as it were, that communicate to them the specific contours and texture
of a particular political or social situation. We speak of the possession of a
good political eye, or nose, or ear, of a political sense which love or
ambition or hate may bring into play, of a sense that crisis and danger sharpen
(or alternatively blunt), to which experience is crucial, a particular gift,
possibly not altogether unlike that of artists or creative writers. We mean
nothing occult or metaphysical; we do not mean a magic eye able to penetrate
into something that ordinary minds cannot apprehend; we mean something
perfectly ordinary, empirical, and quasi-aesthetic in the way that it works.
The gift we mean entails, above all, a capacity for
integrating a vast amalgam of constantly changing, multicolored, evanescent,
perpetually overlapping data, too many, too swift, too intermingled to be
caught and pinned down and labeled like so many individual butterflies. To
integrate in this sense is to see the data (those identified by scientific
knowledge as well as by direct perception) as elements in a single pattern,
with their implications, to see them as symptoms of past and future
possibilities, to see them pragmatically—that is, in terms of what you or
others can or will do to them, and what they can or will do to others or to
you. To seize a situation in this sense one needs to see, to be given a kind of
direct, almost sensuous contact with the relevant data, and not merely to
recognize their general characteristics, to classify them or reason about them,
or analyze them, or reach conclusions and formulate theories about them.
To be able to do this well seems to me to be a gift akin to
that of some novelists, that which makes such writers as, for example, Tolstoy
or Proust convey a sense of direct acquaintance with the texture of life; not
just the sense of a chaotic flow of experience, but a highly developed
discrimination of what matters from the rest, whether from the point of view of
the writer or that of the characters he describes. Above all this is an acute
sense of what fits with what, what springs from what, what leads to what; how
things seem to vary to different observers, what the effect of such experience
upon them may be; what the result is likely to be in a concrete situation of
the interplay of human beings and impersonal forces—geographical or biological
or psychological or whatever they may be. It is a sense for what is qualitative
rather than quantitative, for what is specific rather than general; it is a
species of direct acquaintance, as distinct from a capacity for description or
calculation or inference; it is what is variously called natural wisdom,
imaginative understanding, insight, perceptiveness, and, more misleadingly,
intuition (which dangerously suggests some almost magical faculty), as opposed
to the very different virtues—very great as these are—of theoretical knowledge
or learning, erudition, powers of reasoning and generalization, and
intellectual genius.
The quality I am attempting to describe is that special
understanding of public life (or for that matter private life) which successful
statesmen have, whether they are wicked or virtuous—that which Bismarck had (surely
a conspicuous example, in the last century, of a politician endowed with
considerable political judgment), or Talleyrand or Franklin Roosevelt, or, for
that matter, men such as Cavour or Disraeli, Gladstone or Atatürk, in common
with the great psychological novelists, something which is conspicuously
lacking in men of more purely theoretical genius such as Newton or Einstein or
Russell, or even Freud. This is true even of Lenin, despite the huge weight of
theory by which he burdened himself.
What are we to call this kind of capacity? Practical wisdom,
practical reason, perhaps, a sense of what will “work,” and what will not. It
is a capacity, in the first place, for synthesis rather than analysis, for
knowledge in the sense in which trainers know their animals, or parents their
children, or conductors their orchestras, as opposed to that in which chemists
know the contents of their test tubes, or mathematicians know the rules that
their symbols obey. Those who lack this, whatever other qualities they may
possess, no matter how clever, learned, imaginative, kind, noble, attractive,
gifted in other ways they may be, are correctly regarded as politically
inept—in the sense in which Joseph II of Austria was inept (and he was
certainly a morally better man than, say, his contemporaries Frederick the
Great and the Empress Catherine II of Russia, who were far more successful in
attaining their ends, and far more benevolently disposed toward mankind) or in
which the Puritans, or James II, or Robespierre (or, for that matter, Hitler or
even Lenin in the end) proved to be inept at realizing at least their positive
ends.
What is it that the Emperor Augustus or Bismarck knew and
the Emperor Claudius or Joseph II did not? Very probably the Emperor Joseph was
intellectually more distinguished and far better read than Bismarck, and
Claudius may have known many more facts than Augustus. But Bismarck (or
Augustus) had the power of integrating or synthesizing the fleeting, broken,
infinitely various wisps and fragments that make up life at any level, just as
every human being, to some extent, must integrate them (if he is to survive at
all), without stopping to analyze how he does what he does, and whether there
is a theoretical justification for his activity. Everyone must do it, but
Bismarck did it over a much larger field, against a wider horizon of possible
courses of action, with far greater power—to a degree, in fact, which is quite
correctly described as that of genius. Moreover, the bits and pieces which
require to be integrated—that is, seen as fitting with other bits and pieces,
and not compatible with yet others, in the way in which, in fact, they do fit
and fail to fit in reality—these basic ingredients of life are in a sense too
familiar, we are too much with them, they are too close to us, they form the
texture of the semiconscious and unconscious levels of our life, and for that
reason they tend to resist tidy classification.
Of course, whatever can be isolated, looked at, inspected,
should be. We need not be obscurantist. I do not wish to say or hint, as some
romantic thinkers have, that something is lost in the very act of
investigating, analyzing, and bringing to light, that there is some virtue in
darkness as such, that the most important things are too deep for words, and
should be left untouched, that it is somehow blasphemous to enunciate them.(2) This I believe to be a false and on the whole deleterious doctrine. Whatever
can be illuminated, made articulate, incorporated in a proper science, should
of course be so. “We murder to dissect,” wrote Wordsworth (3)—at times we do; at
other times dissection reveals truths. There are vast regions of reality which
only scientific methods, hypotheses, established truths, can reveal, account
for, explain, and indeed control. What science can achieve must be welcomed. In
historical studies, in classical scholarship, in archaeology, linguistics,
demography, the study of collective behavior, in many other fields of human
life and endeavor, scientific methods can give indispensable information.
I do not hold with those who maintain that natural science,
and the technology based upon it, somehow distorts our vision, and prevents us
from direct contact with reality—”being”—which pre-Socratic Greeks or medieval
Europeans saw face to face. This seems to me an absurd nostalgic delusion. My
argument is only that not everything, in practice, can be—indeed that a great
deal cannot be—grasped by the sciences. For, as Tolstoy taught us long ago, the
particles are too minute, too heterogeneous, succeed each other too rapidly,
occur in combinations of too great a complexity, are too much part and parcel
of what we are and do, to be capable of submitting to the required degree of
abstraction, that minimum of generalization and formalization—idealization—which
any science must exact. After all, Frederick of Prussia and Catherine the Great
founded scientific academies (which are still famous and important) with the
help of French and Swiss scientists—but did not seek to learn from them how to
govern. And although the father of sociology, the eminent Auguste Comte
himself, certainly knew a great many more facts and laws than any politician,
his theories are today nothing but a sad, huge, oddly-shaped fossil in the
stream of knowledge, a kind of curiosity in a museum, whereas Bismarck’s
political gifts—if I may return to this far from admirable man, because he is
perhaps the most effective of all nineteenth-century statesmen—are, alas, only
too familiar among us still. There is no natural science of politics any more
than a natural science of ethics. Natural science cannot answer all questions.
All I am concerned to deny, or at least to doubt, is the
truth of Freud’s dictum that while science cannot explain everything, nothing
else can do so. Bismarck understood something which, let us say, Darwin or
James Clerk Maxwell did not need to understand, something about the public
medium in which he acted, and he understood it as sculptors understand stone or
clay; understood, that is, in this particular case, the potential reactions of
relevant bodies of Germans or Frenchmen or Italians or Russians, and understood
this without, so far as we know, any conscious inference or careful regard to
the laws of history, or laws of any kind, and without recourse to any other
specific key or nostrum—not those recommended by Maistre, or Hegel or Nietzsche
or Bergson or some of their modern irrationalist successors, any more than
those of their enemies, the friends of science. He was successful because he
had the particular gift of using his experience and observation to guess
successfully how things would turn out.
Scientists, at least qua scientists, do not need this
talent. Indeed their training often makes them peculiarly unfit in this
respect. Those who are scientifically trained often seem to hold Utopian
political views precisely because of a belief that methods or models which work
well in their particular fields will apply to the entire sphere of human
action, or if not this particular method or this particular model, then some
other method, some other model of a more or less similar kind. If natural
scientists are at times naive in politics, this may be due to the influence of
an insensibly made, but nevertheless misleading, identification of what works
in the formal and deductive disciplines, or in laboratories, with what works in
the organization of human life.
I repeat: to deny that laboratories or scientific models
offer something—sometimes a great deal—of value for social organization or
political action is sheer obscurantism; but to maintain that they have more to
teach us than any other form of experience is an equally blind form of
doctrinaire fanaticism which has sometimes led to the torture of innocent men
by pseudo-scientific monomaniacs in pursuit of the millennium. When we say of
the men of 1789 in France, or of 1917 in Russia, that they were too
doctrinaire, that they relied too much on theories—whether eighteenth-century
theories such as Rousseau’s, or nineteenth-century theories such as Marx’s—we do
not mean that although these particular theories were indeed defective, better
ones could in principle be discovered, and that these better theories really
would at last do the job of making men happy and free and wise, so that they
would not need, any longer, to depend so desperately on the improvisations of
gifted leaders, leaders who are so few and far between, and so liable to
megalomania and terrible mistakes.
What we mean is the opposite: that theories, in this sense,
are not appropriate as such in these situations. It is as if we were to look
for a theory of tea-tasting, a science of architecture. The factors to be
evaluated are in these cases too many, and it is on skill in integrating them,
in the sense I have described, that everything depends, whatever may be our
creed or our purpose—whether we are utilitarians or liberals, communists or
mystical theocrats, or those who have lost their way in some dark Heideggerian
forest. Sciences, theories no doubt do sometimes help, but they cannot be even a
partial substitute for a perceptual gift, for a capacity for taking in the
total pattern of a human situation, of the way in which things hang together—a
talent to which, the finer, the more uncannily acute it is, the power of
abstraction and analysis seems alien, if not positively hostile.
A scientifically trained observer can of course always
analyze a particular social abuse, or suggest a particular remedy, but he can
do little, as a scientist, to predict what general effects the application of a
given remedy or the elimination of a given source of misery or injustice is
going to have on other—especially on remote—parts of our total social system.
We begin by trying to alter what we can see, but the tremors which our action
starts sometimes run through the entire depth of our society; levels to which
we pay no conscious attention are stirred, and all kinds of unintended results
ensue. It is semi-instinctive knowledge of these lower depths, knowledge of the
intricate connections between the upper surface and other, remoter layers of
social or individual life (which Burke was perhaps the first to emphasize, if
only to turn his perception to his own traditionalist purposes), that is an
indispensable ingredient of good political judgment.
We rightly fear those bold reformers who are too obsessed by
their vision to pay attention to the medium in which they work, and who ignore
imponderables—John of Leiden, the Puritans, Robespierre, Lenin, Hitler, Stalin.
For there is a literal sense in which they know not what they do (and do not
care either). And we are rightly apt to put more trust in the equally bold
empiricists, Henry IV of France, Peter the Great, Frederick of Prussia,
Napoleon, Cavour, Lincoln, Lloyd George, Masaryk, Franklin Roosevelt (if we are
on their side at all), because we see that they understand their material. Is
this not what is meant by political genius? Or genius in other provinces of
human activity? This is not a contrast between conservatism and radicalism, or
between caution and audacity, but between types of gift. As there are
differences of gifts, so there are different types of folly. Two of these types
are in direct contradiction, and in a curious and paradoxical fashion.
The paradox is this: in the realm presided over by the
natural sciences, certain laws and principles are recognized as having been
established by proper methods—that is, methods recognized as reliable by
scientific specialists. Those who deny or defy these laws or methods—people,
say, who believe in a flat earth, or do not believe in gravitation—are quite
rightly regarded as cranks or lunatics. But in ordinary life, and perhaps in
some of the humanities—studies such as history, or philosophy, or law (which
differ from the sciences if only because they do not seem to establish—or even
want to establish—wider and wider generalizations about the world)—those are
Utopian who place excessive faith in laws and methods derived from alien
fields, mostly from the natural sciences, and apply them with great confidence
and somewhat mechanically.
The arts of life—not least of politics—as well as some among
the humane studies turn out to possess their own special methods and
techniques, their own criteria of success and failure. Utopianism, lack of
realism, bad judgment here consist not in failing to apply the methods of
natural science, but, on the contrary, in over-applying them. Here failure
comes from resisting that which works best in each field, from ignoring or
opposing it either in favor of some systematic method or principle claiming
universal validity—say the methods of natural science (as Comte did), or of
historical theology or social development (as Marx did)—or else from a wish to
defy all principles, all methods as such, from simply advocating trust in a
lucky star or personal inspiration: that is, mere irrationalism.
To be rational in any sphere, to display good judgment in
it, is to apply those methods which have turned out to work best in it. What is
rational in a scientist is therefore often Utopian in a historian or a
politician (that is, it systematically fails to obtain the desired result), and
vice versa. This pragmatic platitude entails consequences that not everyone is
ready to accept. Should statesmen be scientific? Should scientists be put in
authority, as Plato or Saint-Simon or H.G. Wells wanted? Equally, we might ask,
should gardeners be scientific, should cooks? Botany helps gardeners, laws of
dietetics may help cooks, but excessive reliance on these sciences will lead
them—and their clients—to their doom. The excellence of cooks and gardeners
still depends today most largely upon their artistic endowment and, like that
of politicians, on their capacity to improvise. Most of the suspicion of
intellectuals in politics springs from the belief, not entirely false, that,
owing to a strong desire to see life in some simple, symmetrical fashion, they
put too much faith in the beneficent results of applying directly to life
conclusions obtained by operations in some theoretical sphere. And the
corollary of this over-reliance on theory, a corollary alas too often corroborated
by experience, is that if the facts—that is, the behavior of living human
beings—are recalcitrant to such experiment, the experimenter becomes annoyed,
and tries to alter the facts to fit the theory, which, in practice, means a
kind of vivisection of societies until they become what the theory originally
declared that the experiment should have caused them to be. The theory is
“saved,” indeed, but at too high a cost in useless human suffering; yet since
it is applied in the first place, ostensibly at least, to save men from the
hardships which, it is alleged, more haphazard methods would bring about, the
result is self-defeating. So long as there is no science of politics in sight,
attempts to substitute counterfeit science for individual judgment not only
lead to failure, and, at times, major disasters, but also discredit the real
sciences, and undermine faith in human reason.
The passionate advocacy of unattainable ideals may, even if
it is Utopian, break open the barriers of blind tradition and transform the
values of human beings, but the advocacy of pseudo-scientific or other kinds of
falsely certified means—methods of the sort advertised by metaphysical or other
kinds of bogus prospectuses—can only do harm. There is a story—I don’t know how
true—that when the Prime Minister Lord Salisbury was one day asked on what
principle he decided whether to go to war, he replied that, in order to decide
whether or not to take an umbrella, he looked at the sky. Perhaps this goes too
far. If a reliable science of political weather-forecasting existed, this
would, no doubt, be condemned as too subjective a procedure. But, for reasons
which I have tried to give, such a science, even if it is not impossible in
principle, is still very far to seek. And to act as if it already existed, or
was merely round the corner, is an appalling and gratuitous handicap to all
political movements, whatever their principles and whatever their purposes—from
the most reactionary to the most violently revolutionary—and leads to avoidable
suffering.
To demand or preach mechanical precision, even in principle,
in a field incapable of it is to be blind and to mislead others. Moreover,
there is always the part played by pure luck—which, mysteriously enough, men of
good judgment seem to enjoy rather more often than others. This, too, is
perhaps worth pondering.
1. "Un
historien est un babillard qui fait des tracasseries aux morts." The
Complete Works of Voltaire, Volume 82 (University of Toronto Press, 1968), p.
452.↩
2. In this spirit Keats wrote: "Do not all charms
fly/At the mere touch of cold philosophy?
Philosophy will clip an Angel's wings,/Conquer all mysteries by rule and line
." Lamia (1820).↩
3. In "The Tables Turned" (1798).↩